The Crack in the Determinist's Egg
A reflection on the limits of cause and effect
thinking, pointing to a dimension of freedom in our
experience.
Thirty-five years ago, Joseph Chilton Pearce
wrote these lines in the introduction to his book,
The Crack in the Cosmic
Egg: "Our
cosmic
egg is the sum total of our notions of what
the world is, notions which define what reality
can
be for us. The crack, then, is a mode of
thinking through which imagination can escape the mundane shell and create a new
cosmic egg." Pearce's book and others with similar thoughts eventually put a
crack in my deterministic model of the
universe.
It's pretty clear that there
are laws governing the universe. We used to do experiments in my freshman
college qualitative chemistry lab that pretty much convinced me of this. I
remember heating potassium chlorate in a test tube to show its decomposition
into oxygen and salt substitute (KCl) in 1956. Students are doing similar
experiments still today. Lots of things behave predictably under carefully
controlled conditions, computers, rockets to the moon, and fractionated
petroleum. But if you don't get the initial conditions just right, all sorts of
unpredictable results may occur.
Now
the determinist's fervent hope is that any unpredictability that results in
events is only due to our lack of information or resources to control the
initial conditions. That is the old view of the universe: it's just like a big
clock, wound up at the beginning and running smoothly, all gears and cogs
connected. It is a model of the universe that guided much of scientific
investigation since the time of Isaac Newton, and even before that, one that led
to an enormous list of laws governing things.
Ironically, in the 20th Century, it
was because of thinking about and attempting to measure the very big and the
very small that scientists were eventually led to see this way of looking at
things as of only limited
usefulness.
Take, for example, trying
to measure the velocity and position of a very small particle, say about the
size of the unit of light, a
photon.
The man, Werner Heisenberg, articulated his
uncertainty
principle about 1925. He pointed out that to
measure the position of a small particle, one had to observe it, and that meant
using light or at least some form of electromagnetic radiation. Observation
involves recording the light that bounces off of a particle to determine its
position. However, once we know the position of a particle using this form of
measurement, we loose track of its velocity, since light too has mass, and the
impact of that mass on the particle changes its velocity in unpredictable ways.
The uncertainty
principle says that we may know the position
OR
the velocity of a particle through
measurement, but not both simultaneously. There is, in effect, a systematic
uncertainty built into the measurement of small
particles.
But there is even more news
about the very small that is unsettling to the clockwork universe
model—our very notion of what a particle
is
got transformed. Eventually, physicists like Schrödinger developed models
of small particles that described not what they looked like, but rather, the
probability that they would be found in such and such a place at a given time.
Electrons "looked like" clouds, but not like any clouds we see on this earth.
They were clouds not of actual particles, but rather of possible positions of
the SAME particle. According to these models, there is an infinitesimally small
but finite possibility that an electron might be
anywhere
at a given time. They might be anywhere, that is, even though their
likely
location is much more
circumscribed.
Einstein gained some of
his fame for his thinking about the very large. Locally (meaning here on Earth),
Euclidian geometry works just fine. Start to measure distances between Earth's
sun and other stars, however, and it appears that a different kind of geometry
is in order, one that seems counterintuitive to common sense. For example, at
these great distances, given a straight line and a point not on that line, more
than one straight line can be drawn through the given point, which lines are
parallel to the given line. Try it with an earth-built clock sometime: clock
geometry, Euclidian.
Equally surprising
was Einstein's posit that the speed of light is constant no matter how fast one
is traveling relative to that light. A little careful thought leads to the
conclusion that whatever the nature of light, it is something very different
from an earthbound object, whose speed varies with the speed of reference of the
observation point. Clock parts certainly don't behave in this way, so once
again, the analogy of the universe as a clock
fails.
Probably the most shocking
experiment of the 20th Century was done by Alan Aspect in 1982 for Bell Labs. It
settled a long-standing debate which started between Einstein and Podolsky and
Rosen. Because quantum mechanics painted such a non-clockwork picture of the
universe, Einstein felt that the theory was incomplete. He died still believing
that there was still a deeper, unexplored level of the universe that did run
like clockwork. In sequence, Podolsky and Rosen, John Bell, and Alan Aspect
showed that Einstein was wrong about that.
The assumption Einstein wanted to make
is technically referred to as the assumption of locality throughout the
universe. In common sense terms, if I clap my hands somewhere on Earth, this
doesn't instantaneously cause an event to occur on the other side of the Earth
without some intervening chain of events. To put it in other common sense terms,
denying locality seems tantamount to affirming some sort of magic. In the end,
however, the experiment done by Aspect showed that there are in fact pairs of
subatomic particles that are somehow "entangled" in just this mysterious way.
Jiggle one particle of such a pair, and the other one will instantly jiggle,
even if it is remote in space and time from the first
particle.
All these different lines of
thinking and experimenting have converged to replace the clock-work model of the
universe with something more nearly akin to a spider web. At least at the level
of subatomic particles, and possibly at every day sizes, everything seems to be
connected, mysteriously, to everything else.
In conclusion, one could say that it
has taken most of the 20th Century for intellectual life to absorb these facts
about the limited validity of the mechanical model for the universe. If, in
fact, there are remote, "hidden" variables for every subatomic event, it seems
much less certain that every event could be predicted if we only knew all the
variables. Oh, there will still be the hordes of logical empiricists pointing to
the huge body of physical laws that science has accumulated, and saying that
these quantum theoretic consequences are of no consequence to our everyday life.
But that seems to me to be a bit like the naive realist who kicks the rock to
prove that it is really there (and possibly hurts his toe in the process). It
misses the point.
Finally, I'll leave
you with just this thought. It is we, the experimenters, who arrange the initial
conditions for our experiments so that they will not fail. It is sheerest
metaphysical speculation to propose that we, too, in all of our complexity, can
be exhibited as the end of a chain of cause and effect. To those with such a
metaphysical position, I simply say, "Show me. It is counter to my intuitive
experience that my actions are entirely determined."
Posted: Sun - April 2, 2006 at 04:37 PM
Of Course It's Boring, Idiot Queen of the Sciences Previous Next Feedback |